We show that Kempen and Harbusch's (Cognition (2003) this issue) arguments against our claims cannot be upheld. On the one hand, their alternative account of our data that is based on the availability of constructions with object-experiencer verbs is not compatible with the literature on the processing of these types of sentences in German. Moreover, their allegation that we failed to conduct an accurate corpus count is simply a misreading of our paper. Insofar, the commentary in no way casts doubt on our claim that grammatical regularities override frequency during online comprehension
We present evidence that the supposed processing advantage for an SVfinO word order over an SOVfin w...
In the computational study of human intelligence, the language sciences are in the unique position o...
Gilquin (2008, What you think ain't what you get: Highly polysemous verbs in mind and language. In J...
We show that Kempen and Harbusch's (Cognition (2003) this issue) arguments against our claims cannot...
We show that Kempen and Harbusch’s (Cognition (2003) this issue) arguments against our claims cannot...
In a recent Cognition paper (Cognition 85 (2002) B21), Bornkessel, Schlesewsky, and Friederici repor...
We show that online processing difficulties induced by word order variations in German cannot be att...
In a recent Cognition paper (Cognition 85 (2002) B21), Bornkessel, Schlesewsky, and Friederici repor...
In the last two decades, the use of quantitative methods in synchronic and diachronic linguistics ha...
We present an overview of several corpus studies we carried out into the frequencies of argument NP ...
Theoretical linguists have traditionally relied on linguistic intuitions such as grammaticality judg...
How are verb-argument structure preferences acquired? Children typically receive very little negativ...
In several languages, non-nominative experiencers tend to appear early on in utterances, which frequ...
In a paper entitled “Against markedness (and what to replace it with)”, Haspelmath argues “that the ...
Häussler J, Bader M. Grammar- Versus Frequency-Driven Syntactic Ambiguity Resolution: The Case of Do...
We present evidence that the supposed processing advantage for an SVfinO word order over an SOVfin w...
In the computational study of human intelligence, the language sciences are in the unique position o...
Gilquin (2008, What you think ain't what you get: Highly polysemous verbs in mind and language. In J...
We show that Kempen and Harbusch's (Cognition (2003) this issue) arguments against our claims cannot...
We show that Kempen and Harbusch’s (Cognition (2003) this issue) arguments against our claims cannot...
In a recent Cognition paper (Cognition 85 (2002) B21), Bornkessel, Schlesewsky, and Friederici repor...
We show that online processing difficulties induced by word order variations in German cannot be att...
In a recent Cognition paper (Cognition 85 (2002) B21), Bornkessel, Schlesewsky, and Friederici repor...
In the last two decades, the use of quantitative methods in synchronic and diachronic linguistics ha...
We present an overview of several corpus studies we carried out into the frequencies of argument NP ...
Theoretical linguists have traditionally relied on linguistic intuitions such as grammaticality judg...
How are verb-argument structure preferences acquired? Children typically receive very little negativ...
In several languages, non-nominative experiencers tend to appear early on in utterances, which frequ...
In a paper entitled “Against markedness (and what to replace it with)”, Haspelmath argues “that the ...
Häussler J, Bader M. Grammar- Versus Frequency-Driven Syntactic Ambiguity Resolution: The Case of Do...
We present evidence that the supposed processing advantage for an SVfinO word order over an SOVfin w...
In the computational study of human intelligence, the language sciences are in the unique position o...
Gilquin (2008, What you think ain't what you get: Highly polysemous verbs in mind and language. In J...